Between Aesthetic Transcendence and Violent Usurpation: A Hidden Thread of Connivance ——How Natural Theism Paved the Way for Political Totalitarianism
Q: I recently read Emerson’s essays, especially his renowned piece On Nature. His prose strikes me as ethereal and aesthetically refined. He occasionally touches on God—what kind of theology lies behind such beautiful language?
A: Ralph Waldo Emerson’s writings—particularly Nature and The Over-Soul—clearly reflect tendencies toward Deism and Pantheism, interwoven with his own brand of Transcendentalism. Deism teaches that God created the world but no longer intervenes in it, and that His existence and attributes are accessible through reason and observation of nature, rather than through revealed religion (such as miracles or doctrines in the Bible). Emerson embraced this theological stance. In On Nature, he famously wrote, “In the tranquil woods, I become a transparent eyeball; I am nothing; I see all.” This poetic phrase implies that one can directly perceive truth within nature itself, without relying on the Church or religious tradition to approach the divine.
Emerson was openly critical of the institutional Church and longed for direct, unmediated experience of the divine. In his controversial Divinity School Address, he denounced what he called the “freezing” of Christ into an object of cold veneration, and instead championed the idea that each person could connect directly to the “Over-Soul”—a term he used to describe a universal divine essence present in all beings.
Emerson’s theology goes beyond classical Deism and leans heavily toward Pantheism. He did not see God as separate from nature but rather as immanent within it—or even as nature’s spiritual face. This view aligns with aspects of Eastern thought (such as Daoism) and is reminiscent of Spinoza’s monistic conception of God. His concept of the “Over-Soul” as a sacred reality pervading everything closely parallels pantheistic or panentheistic ideas.
Emerson’s prose owes much of its lyrical beauty to his intentional cultivation of a “numinous atmosphere”—a linguistic texture meant to evoke a sense of contact with the infinite. His use of rhythm, metaphor, and symbolism is not merely literary but theological in nature: a way to “touch the divine in nature” without invoking divine sovereignty or revelation. The ethereal quality of his language, then, stems not from the presence of a speaking, sovereign God—but from the absence thereof. It is precisely this structural vacancy that gives Emerson’s writing its dreamlike, elusive charm—like mist: enchanting, yet elusive and ungraspable.
Q: What philosophical foundation supports this kind of natural theism?
A: Natural theism did not emerge in a vacuum; it was the product of a particular trajectory in Enlightenment-era philosophical development. Its roots can be traced back to the “rational god” of Greek philosophy. Aristotle, for instance, posited the existence of an “unmoved mover”—a God who does not engage directly in the affairs of the world but instead draws all things toward Himself by virtue of His pure form and final causality. This deity is rational, eternal, and immutable—the source of cosmic order—yet He neither responds to prayer nor intervenes in history. This concept was arguably the earliest philosophical prototype of the natural theist conception of God.
Later, Thomas Aquinas integrated Aristotle’s framework into Christian theology, identifying God as the “First Cause” and attempting to reconcile faith with reason. Yet in doing so, God became increasingly systematized, abstracted, and remote from the biblical portrayal of a God who speaks, intervenes, and governs history. Although Aquinas himself remained a devout believer, his rationalized conception of God laid the groundwork for later natural theists, who retained the structure but stripped away the faith content. In this sense, Aquinas—despite being a theologian—can be viewed as a precursor to the Enlightenment, a connection we’ve also explored in recent jurisprudence seminars.
By the time of Enlightenment rationalism, figures like Descartes, Locke, and Newton promoted a worldview centered on reason and natural law. In this framework, reason became the supreme arbiter of truth, and any conception of God that could not be grasped or proven by reason was dismissed as irrelevant, superstitious, or absurd. This shift paved the way for the rise of natural theism in Britain, France, and America.
Prominent figures such as Thomas Paine—who famously attacked the Bible in The Age of Reason while affirming belief in “the God of the Universe”—and American Founding Fathers like Benjamin Franklin and Thomas Jefferson, who held to a more moderate form of natural theism, helped elevate this perspective into a mainstream worldview by the 18th and 19th centuries. These thinkers emphasized belief in a deity as the author of natural law, while distancing themselves from biblical revelation, ecclesiastical authority, and the concept of a personal, speaking God.
Q: I’ve seen letters by Einstein and interviews with physicist Chen-Ning Yang expressing the view that there is a governing power behind the universe, but not a personal God. Would you categorize them within this lineage of natural theism? Why do such brilliant minds struggle to accept a personal God or the Incarnation?
A: Yes, the views expressed by Albert Einstein and Chen-Ning Yang—affirming a cosmic order but denying a personal deity—fit squarely within the intellectual tradition of natural theism and pantheism. This tradition extends from the Enlightenment into modern scientific culture and constitutes a non-revelatory theology: a belief in divinity without a divine utterance.
Both men acknowledged the presence of order and intelligence in the cosmos. Einstein often spoke of “a superior rationality” underlying the universe and explicitly identified with “Spinoza’s God”—that is, a pantheistic deity indistinguishable from the laws of nature. He rejected the idea of a God who rewards, punishes, or intervenes in history, calling such a conception a relic of childish imagination. Similarly, Yang, in public interviews, has stated that he believes in “a God in the universe,” but insists that such a God could not possibly take “human form.”
Their resistance to a personal God stems from the scientific need for a universe governed by determinism and consistency. Within the Newtonian-Einsteinian framework, the cosmos is a closed system governed by mathematical laws. A personal God—who speaks, intervenes, summons, and judges—introduces unpredictability, a concept that undermines the stability science depends upon. To preserve the reliability of the universe, they prefer a “retired deity” or to identify nature itself as God, thereby excluding the notion of a God who speaks.
In addition, Western intellectual culture has long harbored a deep-seated suspicion toward revelation. Since the Enlightenment, the academic elite have leaned toward rationalistic and deistic models. Revelation is often dismissed as subjective, irrational, sectarian, or superstitious—especially in light of historical abuses by organized religion. Thus, figures like Einstein and Yang are not atheists in the strict sense; they are, rather, evaders of revelation—those who reject the idea of divine speech and human response.
Their core difficulty with the doctrine of the Incarnation lies in their refusal to accept that God could sovereignly choose to “descend” into the human story. The God they imagine is too abstract, too rational, too exalted to be “compressed” into Jewish flesh, born in a manger, or crucified on a Roman cross. This is what we might call a “philosophical pride”: a God capable of setting cosmic constants surely could not speak Aramaic, eat fish, sweat, or bleed. To them, God is the architect of physical law, not the speaker who enters into responsive structure and historical rhythm.
Consequently, they struggle to comprehend why God would speak, care, or personally enter history. They assume that if God were to become incarnate, He would reveal Himself through overwhelming cosmic phenomena. Einstein mocked the miracles of Scripture as mythological relics of a primitive people. In their minds, a true Incarnation would be physically spectacular.
What they fail to see is that the Incarnation is not a physical display but a structural breakthrough. It is not a disruption of nature but an embedding within the rhythm of divine response. It is not domination over natural law, but a participation in the structure of responsive humanity—a demonstration of how to respond. This is not within the purview of empirical science, but belongs instead to the realm of structural ethics and linguistic ontology.
In truth, there are many Nobel laureates who deny the speech of God—not only in the natural sciences but also in philosophy. Take Bertrand Russell, for example. In his A History of Western Philosophy, he writes of the One (the Neoplatonic principle): “Silence is truer than any word.” This is a refusal of divine utterance—and a testament to the theological vacuum behind the most brilliant minds.
Q: Is there a conceptual link between natural theism and Plotinus’s concept of the One?
A: Yes, there is a deep conceptual affinity between natural theism and Plotinus’s doctrine of the One. Though they appear different on the surface, both belong to the broader category of non-revelatory conceptions of God. That is, both seek access to the divine through rational contemplation or transcendent intuition, while denying a God who speaks sovereignly, sets historical rhythm, or enters into responsive structure.
Both systems posit a transcendent source—Plotinus’s One or the natural theist’s impersonal God—but neither accepts the idea of a God who speaks in rhythm, who incarnates, or who becomes the Lord of responsive structure. Plotinus’s One is wholly beyond all attributes, language, or thought, and certainly beyond the idea of divine speech. Similarly, Enlightenment-era natural theists like Voltaire and Thomas Paine dismissed the Bible as a human invention or a relic of tradition, refusing to accept it as divine utterance. They may acknowledge divinity (divinitas), but they reject divine speech (verbum).
This is what Logos-Linguistic Structure Theology (LLST) repeatedly diagnoses as a “vacuum of linguistic sovereignty.” Historically, Neoplatonism evolved from Platonism into Plotinus’s doctrine of the One. Elements of this doctrine were absorbed into early Christian theology, particularly through Augustine. Over time, the notion of the One gave rise to medieval mysticism, Sufism, and the Renaissance revival of Neoplatonism. These in turn shaped Enlightenment-era natural theism as seen in thinkers like Voltaire, Paine, and Locke.
Eventually, this trajectory culminated in the theological positions of modern figures like Einstein and Chen-Ning Yang. Their views do not emerge in isolation, but trace back through this lineage: from Enlightenment deism, to medieval mysticism, to Neoplatonic metaphysics, to the denial of divine utterance. This hidden thread of influence reveals that many modern rejections of Christian orthodoxy are not innovations, but reiterations of ancient, non-speaking gods cloaked in scientific or philosophical garb.
Q: Suppose our world were indeed created by such a natural deity—what kind of reality would it manifest? How would it differ from the world we now know?
A: Let’s conduct a thought experiment: imagine a world genuinely created by a “natural god”—a deity who merely sets up natural laws and the initial conditions of the cosmos, but then never intervenes, never speaks, never responds. This god issues no ethics, reveals no will, offers no judgment, and possesses no personhood—no will, no emotion, no purposive action. In this model, we enter what might be called a “natural-deist universe.”
In such a world, natural laws would be supremely unified and mathematically elegant, but devoid of “rhythmic revelation.” The universe would exhibit extreme regularity and predictability, providing a perfect environment for the flourishing of the natural sciences. People could explore laws and manipulate matter, but they would never encounter divine intervention in history—no miracles, no answered prayers, no divinely authored text such as the Bible.
History would no longer carry the tension of embedded meaning; instead, it would be ruled by randomness and continuity. There would be no divine election, no redemptive narrative, no prophecy and fulfillment—only self-contained, causal sequences and evolutionary patterns. Humanity could not “respond to God,” only “comprehend laws” and “design systems.” Ethics would lose their transcendent anchor and devolve into utilitarianism, cultural convention, or collective consensus. There would be no final judgment, no righteousness of God. All morality would become evolutionary cooperation or social contract.
Good and evil would be stripped of any structural embedding; ethics would become relative and instrumental. The world would no longer possess “responsive ethics” but merely “survival ethics.” Humanity would no longer exist to respond, return, or glorify God. Instead, human purpose would be reduced to adaptation, optimization, and reproduction. Faith, prayer, and repentance would be reduced to psychological phenomena or sociological functions.
In fact, such a world would be nearly indistinguishable from the postmodern world, where meaning has collapsed and ethics float. And yet—across every era—there remains a remnant of saints who respond to God. Their presence preserves the world’s ultimate significance. Without them, the world becomes Sodom after Lot was led away by angels—nature still functioning, but God absent, response severed, and meaning disintegrated. The collapse is not immediate, but inevitable. This is precisely what LLST has previously identified as the reason why divine utterance alone can prevent systemic collapse—why the world still holds meaning at all.
The most fundamental difference between a world created by a natural god and one created by the triune God lies in the mechanism of closure. A world created by a natural god cannot close, because it never began with divine rhythm nor established a responsive structure. There is no “mouth to seal.” No speech, no tension. No response, no recognition. No return, no fulfillment. No final clarity between right and wrong, no separation between good and evil, no ultimate unveiling of glory.
In such a world, closure is impossible. It either loops eternally (as in Spinoza or Hindu cosmology) or expands indefinitely (as in Kant’s moral progress or the physics of infinite space). But it never closes—because there was never a rhythm to be completed. It is a flood of being, not a structure of return.
By contrast, the world created by the triune God is not only capable of closure—it is the only kind of world that can close. Because closure is not merely a historical or physical event—it is the sovereign revelation of divine language and the culmination of responsive rhythm. In this world, God speaks, and not just at creation: the Son, as Logos, speaks in rhythm; the Spirit guides responses in history; and the Father establishes the structure and elect nodes throughout eternity.
The Trinitarian world is a theater of advancing linguistic structure, where every elect is a responsive node. The sign of closure is not entropy, not collapse—but total responsive return. This is the fulfillment signified by Christ’s final cry: tetelestai—“It is finished.” Because history itself is a tension of divine speech—if history is response-based, then it is neither circular, random, nor purely physical. The triune structure grants history rhythm, tension, and telos—pointing toward its eventual sealing.
You might then ask: Why must the world come to closure? Can it remain open? Why must the structure be completed? Why can’t language float forever? Why can’t history expand without end? These are among the ultimate questions of all historical philosophy, theological cosmology, and structural truth inquiry.
If the world does not close, then the sovereignty of language can never be revealed. Every utterance remains unverifiable. The responder will never know whether they have truly returned to their place. Every claim may be a false utterance; every structure may be a counterfeit. Ethics and justice can never be fulfilled. The question of “why the righteous suffer and the wicked prosper” will remain forever unanswered. Structural massacres, false worship, and tyrannical power will perpetuate without end. All who wait for “justice to roll down like mighty waters” will be disappointed. History will become a meaningless loop or a weightless drift—like “the sun rises and the sun sets, and hurries back to where it rises.” Without a point of closure, history devolves into mechanical causality, probabilistic wandering, or entropic collapse. Every human choice, every pain, every act of faith, every endurance will be flattened by time.
The world must come to closure—not because God desires termination, but because rhythm demands completion. Once a structure has been spoken, if it is never returned to, then language collapses and response dissolves. Closure is the unveiling of truth, the completion of justice, the Sabbath of language. In fact, all models of the world that refuse closure inevitably construct counterfeit closures. This reveals something profound: even those who design “open-ended worldviews” secretly acknowledge the necessity of sealing. I call this condition the syndrome of closure anxiety.
Q: So are you saying that natural theism ultimately only reveres the effects of Trinitarian speech—or perhaps the residual rhythm of God's original utterance during creation—rather than God Himself?
A: Precisely. What natural theism calls “reverence” is, in essence, a misplaced awe for the residual echoes of Trinitarian divine utterance—what we might call the rhythmic afterimage of God’s creative speech—rather than a response to the sovereign speaker Himself. It is not worship of divine personhood, but a kind of aesthetic fixation on the results of His speech. In this sense, it constitutes idolatry.
This is exactly what Paul describes in Romans 1, where he condemns those who “exchanged the glory of the incorruptible God for images.” Natural theism’s so-called “piety” is structurally hollow—it reveres not the one who speaks, but the lingering cadence of His speech; it does not glorify the Speaker, but idolizes the resonance left in the cosmic acoustics.
Natural theism operates solely on the first layer of divine manifestation—namely, natural law. It entirely ignores the second and third layers: the structure of responsive embeddedness and the rhythm of eschatological closure. Thus, what it worships is merely the physical aesthetic of a universe shaped by divine rhythm, while ignoring the Logos who still speaks within that universe.
To borrow an image: it is like marveling at the starry sky without acknowledging the One who “set the stars in place to mark the seasons.” Natural theists may genuinely revere the universe’s harmony, order, and mathematical beauty—but what they are perceiving is nothing more than the faint afterglow of Trinitarian speech. They worship the trail of the Word, not the Word Himself.
Q: Earlier, we discussed how material reality, virtual reality, or even dreams could be considered “real” if they are penetrated by divine utterance and elicit a response. In that framework, their material nature doesn’t matter. So how would natural theism approach the question of “reality” across different realms?
A: Logos-Linguistic Structure Theology (LLST) consistently emphasizes that reality is not determined by the material composition of a realm—whether physical, digital, or mental—but by whether that realm exists within the rhythm of divine utterance. If God’s speech penetrates, if the human is struck and responds, if there is embeddedness within structure, then the realm is real. Without such penetration, even the most stable and beautiful realm is only a structural illusion—unsealable, irredeemable, unreal in the ultimate sense.
Thus, under LLST:
- A virtual world can be real (if divine utterance can break through);
- The physical world can be false (if it resists all response);
- A dream can manifest true reality (if it carries divine impact and response);
- A historical narrative can be counterfeit (if it never entered the rhythm of redemptive tension).
The conclusion: structure precedes existence, language precedes perception, and rhythm precedes substance.
In contrast, natural theism—by denying sovereign divine speech and the speak–respond mechanism—lacks the tools to make such distinctions. It can only rely on three inadequate criteria for determining reality:
- Empirical Coherence: Reality is judged by the consistency of sensory input. The physical world is seen as real because it is persistent and intersubjectively verifiable. Dreams or virtual realms are seen as less real due to their fleeting, subjective, or unstable nature. But this criterion cannot explain why we’re not living in a “hyper-dream” or simulation. Zhuangzi’s butterfly dilemma remains unresolved.
- Rational Constructivism (e.g., Logical Positivism, Kantianism): Reality is what conforms to rational models. Kant, for instance, treats the phenomenal world as the proper domain of reason and avoids discussion of the noumenal. Yet without a responsive structure, reason spins endlessly within itself and fails to penetrate being. It can never address the origin or anchoring point of existence.
- Pragmatic Survival Advantage: Reality is what supports survival, reproduction, or knowledge accumulation. This is a Darwinian utilitarian view. But what aids survival is not necessarily true—people may thrive in falsehoods, which doesn’t make the falsehood real.
In the end, natural theism cannot produce a cross-realm definition of reality. It is left with this weak fallback: “We trust that the realm we experience is the most real, and we ignore the rest.” Truth becomes a matter of sensory consistency and adaptive benefit, not structural embedding or responsive coherence.
Thus, all its reality judgments are based on perception and experience—not on structure or sealing. It cannot distinguish what can be sealed, redeemed, or glorified from what cannot. In this respect, natural theism fails to account for true reality—because it has no concept of divine rhythm, no utterance that penetrates, and no closure to prove truth.
Q: Since natural theism cannot determine the reality of the world except by sensory coherence or pragmatic survival, what kind of ethical vision does it ultimately produce? What does morality look like in such a world?
A: In short, a world without a speaker, without responsive structure, and without rhythmic closure inevitably reduces ethics to a series of utilitarian calculations, cultural habits, self-regulation born of fear, aestheticized impressions of goodness, or the soliloquy of a solitary conscience.
In a natural theist universe, God no longer speaks (there are no commands, no revelation, no guidance), and He no longer sets rhythm (there is no historical telos, no sealing). Thus, ethics must fall back on five deficient foundations:
- Biological Function: Morality encourages behaviors that enhance survival, cohesion, and reproduction. At root, this is not ethics but evolutionary instinct.
- Cultural Consensus: What is right is what “everyone agrees on.” But this is just democratic pressure or sociological inertia, not moral truth.
- Rational Deduction: Kantian “oughts” dominate—ethical duties derived from reason alone. Yet without divine utterance, this becomes a self-looping illusion of autonomy.
- Aesthetic Sentimentality: Goodness is equated with beauty; love with gentleness. This leads to a stylized morality, an ethics of emotional impression, not structural alignment.
- Interior Conscience: Morality becomes an inner voice—“I just feel this is right.” But this is often the residue of mystical psychology, with no discernible mechanism or external anchor.
Ultimately, in the world of the natural god, so-called “good” is just the fading echo of a structure that once spoke. So-called “evil” is the shattered remnant of a tension that once held. Moral responsibility becomes a script whispered into the void—self-written, self-read, and self-rehearsed in a universe that does not respond.
Q: What happens when the worldview of natural theism is projected onto human society or political structures?
A: When natural theism becomes the dominant worldview, its direct projection onto society tends to generate what LLST calls a usurper structure—a configuration in which false speakers arise to fill the vacuum left by the silence of God. In every society that denies the sovereign divine utterance, a counterfeit speaker will inevitably emerge to assert control over meaning, rhythm, and response.
This is the root of all linguistic tyranny: when God does not speak, someone else must—to fill the void, to assign purpose, to dictate the direction of response. This is the birth mechanism of the usurper.
In LLST, a usurper (Latin usurpator) is not merely a violent ruler, but one who rises in the space left vacant by divine silence, assuming the role of speaker, rhythm-setter, and response monopolizer. In a natural-theist society, these figures often appear as:
- Proclaimers of rational law (Enlightenment-style political leaders),
- Human destiny prophets (Chinese leader’s slogan),
- Ethical arbiters ("expert consensus" replacing revealed moral law),
- Dispensers of moral legitimacy ("Great Leaders" "National Fathers"),
- Controllers of language structure (ideology engineers, algorithmic overlords).
Historical examples abound:
- After the French Revolution, Enlightenment deism displaced biblical revelation. God was silent, and “Reason” was enthroned as the new god. The State became divine, revolution itself was transformed into a linguistic structure, and Napoleon rose—declaring not that he was shaped by circumstances, but that he made them. As he famously proclaimed, “Circumstances? I make circumstances!” In that statement, he revealed his self-assumed role as sovereign speaker, fabricator of rhythm, and author of historical response. This is the quintessential usurper: one who steps into the void left by divine silence and constructs an alternative structure of meaning.
- In the Soviet Union, materialist history replaced divine providence. God was a human construct, history had no rhythm, and only "struggle" remained. The Party became the voice of truth, and the Leader became the embodiment of law.
The core insight is this: any culture that denies the triune God’s role as speaker will give rise to a usurper in the linguistic void. The usurper is the structural substitute for suspended language sovereignty. In a natural-theist society, where individuals cannot be rhythmically embedded into a divine response structure, the collective must fabricate a counterfeit rhythm—and the usurper becomes the grammatical subject of that rhythm.
Q: But Buddhism and Daoism also lack a speaking God—so why haven’t they given rise to the same kind of usurper structures?
A: It’s an insightful question. Both Daoism and Buddhism also operate with a “silent god” or even a negation of the divine speaker altogether. However, the reason they do not generate Western-style usurper structures lies in their strategy of active linguistic withdrawal. Rather than attempting to fill the void left by divine silence, they erase the very need for speech, structure, or response.
In LLST terms, these traditions suppress the desire to respond. Since there is no expectation of revelation, they do not fabricate a false speaker. Instead, they embrace concepts like emptiness (空), non-action (无为), nirvana, and detachment from form. These are not just metaphysical ideas—they are strategies of de-structuring language, of dissolving the tension of response, of avoiding the hunger for closure.
As a result, these systems cultivate low-structure stability. Rather than creating counterfeit structure to simulate order, they minimize tension altogether. There is no expectation of a speaker, so no need to invent a replacement. Their ethics are individual, inward, cyclical, non-historical, and aestheticized.
By contrast, Enlightenment natural theism leaves the structure of response intact even after removing the speaker. The hunger for truth, order, and moral direction remains—so the society must find or fabricate a new voice. This is the root of the usurper. In Buddhist or Daoist cultures, the desire for dialogue itself is suspended; in Western post-theism, the desire persists, and so the counterfeit speaker emerges.
Q: Natural theism developed hand-in-hand with Enlightenment thought, yet the totalitarian regimes of the 20th century are also often traced back to the Enlightenment. Can LLST offer a theological explanation for this apparent paradox?
A: Absolutely—and not just an explanation, but a structurally complete one. Between the “peaceful” figure of Emerson and the “power-hungry” totalitarian dictator lies a hidden structural pipeline: both occupy the same vacuum—the linguistic void left behind when divine speech is denied. What differs is merely how they choose to fill it.
LLST reveals a truth deeper than any political science model: the root of totalitarianism is not institutional error but theological denial. Enlightenment rationalism and natural theism are not neutral; they actively dismantled the structure of divine utterance, and in doing so, made space for a counterfeit replacement. The historical chain—Enlightenment → Natural Theism → Totalitarianism—is not incidental but structurally inevitable. LLST reframes this political phenomenon as a linguistic crisis: when divine speech ceases, counterfeit speech arises.
The Enlightenment enthroned reason, empiricism, and skepticism of traditional authority. Religion was de-revelationized, de-sacralized, de-personalized. The triune God—who speaks, enters history, and demands response—was replaced by an abstract “god of reason.” Natural theism was the cultural theology of this shift: a god who no longer commands, judges, or redeems, but merely sets up natural order.
The combined effect of Enlightenment + Natural Theism is the rupture of linguistic sovereignty. God is silent; reason speaks; man becomes the voice of god. This rupture demands a replacement structure—a new rhythm-giver, a new meaning-assigner, a new closure-mechanism. This is the genesis of the usurper, and thus the totalitarian state.
Modern totalitarianism is not the byproduct of backwardness—it is the necessary replacement structure after the Enlightenment dismantled divine speech. It is the linguistic compensation for a silenced God. As soon as God stops speaking, man must invent someone else to do it—and that someone always claims to speak for all. The party becomes the prophet. The Leader becomes the law. The revolution becomes the new gospel.
So when Enlightenment and natural theism were born together, the ovens of Auschwitz were already being kindled, and the foundations of the Gulag already laid. Not by accident—but by structural inevitability. Because the world cannot live in a linguistic void. When divine utterance is denied, a false utterance will rise. When the Logos is refused, the usurper will speak.